Results for 'Saule T. Omarova'

935 found
Order:
  1.  17
    “Private” Means to “Public” Ends: Governments as Market Actors.Saule T. Omarova & Robert C. Hockett - 2014 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 15 (1):53-76.
    Many people recognize that governments can play salutary roles in relation to markets by “overseeing” market behavior from “above,” or supplying foundational “rules of the game” from “below.” It is probably no accident that these widely recognized roles also sit comfortably with traditional conceptions of government and market, pursuant to which people tend categorically to distinguish between “public” and “private” spheres of activity. There is a third form of government action that receives less attention than forms and, however, possibly owing (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  21
    Sequential processes and the shapes of reaction time distributions.Saul Sternberg & Benjamin T. Backus - 2015 - Psychological Review 122 (4):830-837.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  67
    Impressions, Ideas, and Fictions.Saul Traiger - 1987 - Hume Studies 13 (2):381-399.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:381 IMPRESSIONS, IDEAS, AND FICTIONS I. Introduction Under the heading of "fiction," Selby-Bigge's index to Hume's Treatise of Human Nature lists no fewer than seventeen distinct fictions. There is the fiction of perfect equality, of continued and distinct existence, of substance and matter, of substantial forms, accidents, faculties and occult qualities, the fiction of personal identity, and many others. The notion of a fiction is central in Hume's philosophy. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  4. (1 other version)Identity and necessity.Saul A. Kripke - 1971 - In Milton Karl Munitz (ed.), Identity and individuation. New York,: New York University Press. pp. 135-164.
    are synthetic a priori judgements possible?" In both cases, i~thas usually been t'aken for granted in fife one case by Kant that synthetic a priori judgements were possible, and in the other case in contemporary,'d-". philosophical literature that contingent statements of identity are ppss. ible. I do not intend to deal with the Kantian question except to mention:ssj~".
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   444 citations  
  5.  56
    Dogwhistles and Figleaves: How Manipulative Language Spreads Racism and Falsehood.Jennifer Saul - 2024 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    It is widely accepted that political discourse in recent years has become more openly racist and more filled with wildly implausible conspiracy theories. Dogwhistles and Figleaves explores certain ways in which such changes—both of which defied previously settled norms of political speech—have been brought about. Jennifer Saul shows that two linguistic devices, dogwhistles and figleaves, have played a crucial role. Some dogwhistles (such as “88,” used by Nazis online to mean “Heil Hitler”) serve to disguise messages that would otherwise be (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6.  29
    LISA T. SARASOHN, Gassendi's Ethics: Freedom in a Mechanistic Universe. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996. Pp. xii+236. ISBN 0-8014-2947-1. £35.50. [REVIEW]Saul Fisher - 1998 - British Journal for the History of Science 31 (3):361-375.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Racial Figleaves, the Shifting Boundaries of the Permissible, and the Rise of Donald Trump.Jennifer M. Saul - 2017 - Philosophical Topics 45 (2):97-116.
    The rise to power of Donald Trump has been shocking in many ways. One of these was that it disrupted the preexisting consensus that overt racism would be death to a national political campaign. In this paper, I argue that Trump made use of what I call “racial figleaves”—additional utterances that provide just enough cover to give reassurance to voters who are racially resentful but don’t wish to see themselves as racist. These figleaves also, I argue, play a key role (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  8.  75
    Humean Testimony.Saul Traiger - unknown - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 74 (2):135-149.
    Epistemology is in the business of formulating norms of acceptable belief. We typically arrive at beliefs through inference. So epistemology is concerned with our inferential practices. Making inferences is something individuals do. If I believe the premises of an argument and you know how to infer something from those premises, it doesn't follow that you will draw the inference, unless you believe the premises. It appears, then, that all the important epistemic work goes on in individual agents. When we build (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  9. Politically Significant Terms and Philosophy of Language.Jennifer Saul - 2012 - In Anita M. Superson & Sharon L. Crasnow (eds.), Out from the Shadows: Analytical Feminist Contributions to Traditional Philosophy. New York, US: Oxford University Press.
    Philosophers of language have tended to focus on examples that are not politically significant in any way. We spend a lot of time analyzing natural kind terms: We think hard about “water” and “pain” and “arthritis.” But we don’t think much about the far more politically significant kind terms (natural or social—it's a matter for dispute) like “race,” “sex,” “gender,” “woman,” “man,” “gay,” and “straight.” In this essay, I will try to show, using the example of “woman,” that it's worth (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  10.  3
    Wittgenstein: la mosaïque des fondements.Nicholas Saul-Tarrade - 2024 - Paris: Michalon éditeur.
    Inspiré par son intérêt pour la discipline naissante de l'ingénierie aéronautique, Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889-1951) se plonge dans l'étude de la logique et des fondements mathématiques. Son cheminement intellectuel et existentiel le conduira à redécouvrir l'importance du sens commun et de l'intuition pour éclairer la mosaïque des accords sensibles entre humains. Ne renonçant jamais aux exigences de la rationalité, il s'intéresse à l'anthropologie et au langage, à l'éthique et à l'esthétique, au droit et à l'art, refusant la rigidification dogmatique et le (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  29
    Two Concepts of Effort.Saul Smilansky - 2022 - Philosophia 50 (5):2663-2673.
    I distinguish between two concepts of effort, E-effort and T-effort. E-effort is the familiar one, which focuses on the experiential qualities of making an effort (such the energy and time we put into effort making, or the hardship we endure). Teleological effort (or T-effort) is the motivated and active focus on the intended purpose or goal of the effort; the aim to do what it takes to reach the target of the effort. When we make a T-effort we concentrate on (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  5
    Special Volume on Reformulation, dedicated to the memory of Saul Amarel, 1928–2002.T. Ellman - 2005 - Artificial Intelligence 162 (1-2):1.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  27
    Book Review:Jefferson. Saul K. Padover. [REVIEW]T. V. Smith - 1942 - Ethics 53 (1):69-.
  14.  5
    Evidence.Howard Saul Becker - 2017 - London: University of Chicago Press.
    Howard S. Becker is a master of his discipline. His reputation as a teacher, as well as a sociologist, is supported by his best-selling quartet of sociological guidebooks: Writing for Social Scientists, Tricks of the Trade, Telling About Society, and What About Mozart? What About Murder? It turns out that the master sociologist has yet one more trick up his sleeve—a fifth guidebook, Evidence. Becker has for seventy years been mulling over the problem of evidence. He argues that social scientists (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  24
    Book Review:Reveille for Radicals. Saul D. Alinsky. [REVIEW]T. V. Smith - 1946 - Ethics 57 (1):69-.
  16.  9
    Proustian uncertainties: on reading and rereading In search of lost time.Saul Friedländer - 2020 - New York: Other Press.
    An award-winning historian revisits Marcel Proust's masterpiece in this essay on literature and memory, exploring the question of identity-that of the novel's narrator and Proust's own. In this engaging reexamination of In Search of Lost Time, Saul Friedländer considers how the narrator defines himself, how this compares to what we know of Proust himself, and what the significance is of these various points of commonality and divergence. We know, for example, that the author did not hide his homosexuality, but the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  77
    Naming and Necessity By Saul Kripke Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1980, 172 pp., £7.95. [REVIEW]T. L. S. Sprigge - 1981 - Philosophy 56 (217):431-.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  69
    An Intensional Theory of Truth: An Informal Report.Roy T. Cook - 2020 - Philosophical Forum 51 (2):115-126.
    Saul Kripke’s theory of truth suffers from expressive limitations – in particular, there are no extensional operators within that framework that allow one to characterize those sentences that fail to receive a truth value within the framework. Especially worrisome is the fact that there is no operator that outputs true on exactly the paradoxical sentences. In this paper I extend Kripke’s approach via the addition of extensional operators, which allows us to characterize many (but not all) such sentences, including the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19. Semantic Features of the Identities of Persons.Mark T. Brown - 1987 - Dissertation, University of Kansas
    The chief goal of this dissertation is to attain some clarity with respect to the interconnected issues which constitute the problem of personal identity. The logical and linguistic categories developed by Saul Kripke provide the tools through which these issues can be separated and put into perspective. In the first two chapters I examine the modal and other semantic features of rigid singular terms and such rigid predicates as natural kind terms. I defend both the transworld identity of named individuals (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  9
    David a-t-il régné du vivant de Saül? Étude littéraire et historique de II Sm 2, 1-11.Jean-Claude Haelewyck - 1995 - Revue Théologique de Louvain 26 (2):165-184.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Reference and Necessity: A Rand-Kripke Synthesis? [REVIEW]Roderick T. Long - 2000 - Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 7 (1):209 - 228.
    The widespread assumption among academic philosophers that no truth can be simultaneously necessary and factual, founded on the analytic-synthetic dichotomy, was challenged from outside the profession by Ayn Rand and Leonard Peikoff in the 1960s, and from within the profession by Saul Kripke and Hilary Putnam in the 1970s. Gregory M. Browne's book Necessary Factual Truth represents a long-overdue attempt to synthesize the Rand-Peikoff and Kripke-Putnam approaches into an integrated theory. While Browne's project is partially successful, it gives up one (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22. Czy Saul Kripke mógłby być fenomenologiem?Paweł Grabarczyk - 2003 - Filozofia Nauki 1.
    In this article I am trying to compare the methods of phenomenology and analytic philosophy. Such a general comparison is of course impossible in a small article. In order to make it possible I am comparing selected authors. Phenomenology is thus represented by Husserl and Ingarden, analytic philosophy by Putnam and Kripke (they are chosen because of their realism and essentialism). I am trying to analyze the way the authors describe their methods. First I am analyzing analytic philosophy from the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  42
    History of Medicine Tom Rivers. Reflections on a Life in Medicine and Science. An Oral History. By Saul Benison. Pp. xxi + 682. Cambridge, Mass. and London: M.I.T. Press. 1967. 140s. [REVIEW]Edwin Clarke - 1968 - British Journal for the History of Science 4 (2):185-186.
  24.  38
    « Suivre une règle » chez Wittgenstein : un paradoxe sceptique pour Saul Kripke.Paul Bernier - 1988 - Philosophiques 15 (2):390-404.
    Dans cet article, nous considérons un paradoxe sceptique que Saul Kripke a attribué à Wittgenstein. Nous critiquons la solution directe proposée par Colin McGinn , qui a recours à la théorie causale de la référence, et nous montrons pourquoi cette solution n'est pas satisfaisante. La solution sceptique que Kripke prête à Wittgenstein est ensuite discutée à la lumière de nos considérations sur la théorie causale, ce qui nous amène à constater qu'elle est aussi insuffisante. Nous concluons en montrant que nous (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Don't Go to Lawyers for Moral Guidance.Shane Ralston - 2022 - In Brett Coppenger, Joshua Heter & Daniel Carr (eds.), Better Call Saul and Philosophy: I Think Therefore I Scam. United States: Carus Books. pp. 13-20.
    If it were followed by “I’m a president,” Richard Nixon’s televised denial (“I am not a crook”) would be tantamount to Jimmy McGill’s self-portrayal in Better Call Saul. Out of the crooked timber of humanity, an honest president or an ethical lawyer rarely emerges. They’re like needles in a haystack. Nevertheless, it’s worthwhile to search for these rare artifacts and, in the process, ask, “Why do so many lawyers (and presidents) fall from grace, transforming into morally bad or corrupt actors?” (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  16
    What Historical Theorists Haven't Shown.Paolo Dau - 1983 - Dialectica 37 (1):35-56.
    SummaryThis paper defends the descriptive theory of reference against recent criticisms. Saul Kripke has argued through a series of counterexamples that the descriptive theory may assign a referent to a speaker's use of a name when there is no referent, and may assign the wrong referent, or no referent at all, when there really is a referent. These conclusions follow, however, only if the speaker is not permitted to use subordinating descriptions, by means of which he borrows his reference from (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. And they ain't outside the head either.John Koethe - 1992 - Synthese 90 (1):27-53.
    According to a classical view in the philosophy of language, the reference of a term is determined by a property of the term which supervenes on the history of its use. A contrasting view is that a term's reference is determined by how it is properly interpreted, in accordance with certain constraints or conditions of adequacy on interpretations. Causal theories of reference of the sort associated with Hilary Putnam, Saul Kripke and Michael Devitt are versions of the first view, while (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Teria o metro-padrão um metro?Kherian Gracher - 2015 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 19 (3):465-474.
    Saul Kripke (1972) argued for the existence of a priori propositions that are contingently true. Kripke uses the example of a case presented by Wittgenstein (1953) about the Standard Meter of Paris. The Standard Meter is an object to determine the standard lenght, in the measure system, of a one meter unit. Wittgenstein argued that we can’t affirm that the Standard Meter has one meter, since it is the standard for measure and works as a rule in the language. Therefore, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Contexts and pornography.Mari Mikkola - 2008 - Analysis 68 (4):316-320.
    Jennifer Saul has argued that the speech acts approach to pornography, where pornography has the illocutionary force of subordinating women, is undermined by that very approach: if pornographic works are speech acts, they must be utterances in contexts; and if we take contexts seriously, it follows that only some pornographic viewings subordinate women. In an effort to defend the speech acts approach, Claudia Bianchi argues that Saul focuses on the wrong context to fix pornography’s illocutionary force. In response, I defend (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  30.  43
    Penned In.Richard Stern - 1986 - Critical Inquiry 13 (1):1-32.
    “Writers don’t have tasks,” said Saul Bellow in a Q-and-A. “They have inspiration.”Yes, at the typewriter, by the grace of discipline and the Muse, but here, on Central Park South, in the Essex House’s bright Casino on the Park, inspiration was not running high.Not that attendance at the forty-eight PEN conference was a task. It was rather what Robertson Davies called “collegiality.” “A week of it once every five years,” he said, “should be enough.” He, Davies, had checked in early, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  4
    Журнал «Эпистемология и философия науки» Контуры замысла.И. T. Касавин - 2004 - Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 1 (1):5-14.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  82
    Wittgenstein on accord.José L. Zalabardo - 2003 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 84 (3):311–329.
    The paper deals with the interpretation of Wittgenstein's views on the power of occurrent mental states to sort objects or states of affairs as in accord or in conflict with them, as presented in the rule-following passages of the Philosophical Investigations. I shall argue first that the readings advanced by Saul Kripke and John McDowell fail to provide a satisfactory construal of Wittgenstein's treatment of a platonist account of this phenomenon, according to which the sorting power of occurrent mental states (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  33. Loar's defence of physicalism.Stephen Law - 2004 - Ratio 17 (1):60-67.
    Brian Loar believes he has refuted all those antiphysicalist arguments that take as their point of departure observations about what is or isn't conceivable. I argue that there remains an important, popular and plausible-looking form of conceivability argument that Loar has entirely overlooked. Though he may not have realized it, Saul Kripke presents, or comes close to presenting, two fundamentally different forms of conceivability argument. I distinguish the two arguments and point out that while Loar has succeeded in refuting one (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  34. Moral Constraints on Gender Concepts.N. G. Laskowski - 2020 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 23 (1):39-51.
    Are words like ‘woman’ or ‘man’ sex terms that we use to talk about biological features of individuals? Are they gender terms that we use to talk about non-biological features e.g. social roles? Contextualists answer both questions affirmatively, arguing that these terms concern biological or non-biological features depending on context. I argue that a recent version of contextualism from Jennifer Saul that Esa Diaz-Leon develops doesn't exhibit the right kind of flexibility to capture our theoretical intuitions or moral and political (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  35. Semantic Realism and the Argument from Motivational Internalism.Alexander Miller - 2012 - In Richard Schantz (ed.), Prospects for Meaning. Walter de Gruyter. pp. 345-362.
    In his 1982 book Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language, Saul Kripke develops a famous argument that purports to show that there are no facts about what we mean by the expressions of our language: ascriptions of meaning, such as “Jones means addition by ‘+’” or Smith means green by ‘green’”, are according to Kripke’s Wittgenstein neither true nor false. Kripke’s Wittgenstein thus argues for a form of non-factualism about ascriptions of meaning: ascriptions of meaning do not purport to state (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  36. Moogles, and Chocobos, and Kripke? Oh My! Some Basic Issues in Contemporary Philosophy of Language, Kupo!Richard Brown - manuscript
    [originally written for Final Fantasy and Philosophy but I was not happy with editorial decisions and decided to let it remain unpublished] Everyone knows that moogles are disgustingly cute. I know people who would kill to be able to have one in real life, but could there really be moogles? Say, for instance, that archeologists discovered a species of animal in some remote land that completely resembled the chocobo in every way. Would that count as discovering that the beloved Final (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  15
    Apories de l'Identité Narrative.Claude Romano - 2024 - Études Ricoeuriennes / Ricoeur Studies 15 (1):62-85.
    La notion d’identité narrative place la possibilité de l’identité à soi (ou identité-idem) avec celle du changement. Mais a-t-on besoin d’une médiation « dialectique », comme la désigne Ricœur, entre identité et changement? Seulement si l’identité est supposée exclure le changement. Or, tel n’est pas le cas de l’identité au sens le plus fondamental du terme, l’identité numérique. La seconde difficulté tient à ce que Ricœur paraît souvent rabattre l’une sur l’autre les notions d’histoire et de narration. Nous sommes des (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  79
    De Sousa On Kripke and Theoretical Identities.R. M. Yoshida - 1975 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 5 (1):137-141.
    In the by now well known talks he gave at Princeton, Saul Kripke claimed that “[t]heoretical identities … are generally identities involving two rigid designators and therefore are examples of the necessary a posteriori.” 253-355; A rigid designator is an expression that designates the same object in all possible worlds when it is used. So Kripke is claiming that ‘Water is H20’ and ‘Heat is the motion of molecules’ are generally identities involving expressions like ‘water’ and ‘the motion of molecules’ (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  43
    Do Proper Names Always Rigidly Designate?Donald Nute - 1978 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8 (3):475 - 484.
    Many philosophers have claimed possible worlds semantics is incoherent because of insoluble problems involved in the notion of identifying a single individual in different worlds. One frequent approach to trans-world identification has been to assume that all the possible worlds, complete with their populations, are described by means of qualities alone prior to our considering the question of identification of the same individual in each world in which it exists. If we interpret possible worlds semantics in this way, trans-world identification (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. General Terms as Rigid Designators.Bernard Linsky - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 128 (3):655-667.
    According to Scott Soames’ Beyond Rigidity, there are two important pieces of unfinished business left over from Saul Kripke’s influential Naming and Necessity. Soames reads Kripke’s arguments about names as primarily negative, that is, as proving that names don’t have a meaning expressible by definite descriptions or clusters of them. The famous Kripkean doctrine that names are rigid designators is really only part of the negative case. The thesis that names refer to the same object with respect to every possible (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  41.  8
    Unancestral voice.Owen Barfield - 1965 - San Rafael, CA: Barfield Press.
    "In the great English tradition of the lay specialist, Barfield, a lawyer, modernizes the Platonic dialogue format to focus on the philosophic problems of reality and ways of knowing.. This is the solvent mind at its best-distinguished exchanges giving provocative, open-ended results at every point. Highly recommended. of permanent value." Owen Barfield, who died in 1997 shortly after entering his hundredth year, was one of the seminal minds of the twentieth century, of whom C. S. Lewis wrote "he towers above (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  13
    Worlds apart: a dialogue of the 1960's.Owen Barfield - 1963 - San Rafael, CA: Barfield Press.
    "In the great English tradition of the lay specialist, Barfield, a lawyer, modernizes the Platonic dialogue format to focus on the philosophic problems of reality and ways of knowing.. This is the solvent mind at its best-distinguished exchanges giving provocative, open-ended results at every point. Highly recommended. of permanent value." -Choice: Books for College Libraries Owen Barfield, who died in 1997 shortly after entering his hundredth year, was one of the seminal minds of the twentieth century, of whom C. S. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  15
    Statuen hoher Würdenträger im Stadtbild Konstantinopels.Franz Alto Bauer - 2003 - Byzantinische Zeitschrift 96 (2):493-514.
    Zusammenfassung Der dargelegte Befund deutet darauf hin, daß es in Konstantinopel wie in Rom und anderen Provinzmetropolen zahlreiche Statuen hoher Beamter und Würdenträger gab. Allerdings fehlt ein entsprechender Befund für die Regierungszeit Konstantins d. Gr.; erst unter der Regierung Konstantius' II. lassen sich die ersten Beamtenstatuen feststellen. Das mag am Zufall der Überlieferung liegen, deckt sich aber immerhin damit, daß erst unter diesem Kaiser der Rahmen für eine breite magistratische Repräsentation gegeben war. Unter Konstantius II. wurde der Konstantinopler Senat zahlenmäßig (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. The fixed point non-classical theory of truth value gaps by S. Kripke.Artyom Ukhov - 2017 - Vestnik SPbSU. Philosophy and Conflict Studies 33 (2):224-233.
    The article is about one of the vital problem for analytic philosophy which is how to define truth value for sentences which include their own truth predicate. The aim of the article is to determine Saul Kripke’s approach to widen epistemological truth to create a systemic model of truth. Despite a lot of work on the subject, the theme of truth is no less relevant to modern philosophy. With the help of S. Kripke’s article “Outline of the Theory of Truth” (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Notions of nothing.Stacie Friend - 2016 - In Friend Stacie (ed.).
    Book synopsis: New work on a hot topic by an outstanding team of authors At the intersection of several central areas of philosophy It is the linguistic job of singular terms to pick out the objects that we think or talk about. But what about singular terms that seem to fail to designate anything, because the objects they refer to don't exist? We can employ these terms in meaningful thought and talk, which suggests that they are succeeding in fulfilling their (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  46. Tertiumne datur? Possessive pronouns and the bipartition of the lexicon.T. E. Zimmerman - 2004 - In Hans Kamp & Barbara Hall Partee (eds.), Context-dependence in the analysis of linguistic meaning. Boston: Elsevier. pp. 319--332.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  66
    “… or is the question of being at once the most basic and the most concrete?” On the ambitions and responsibilities of contemporary American philosophy.Albert Borgmann - 2010 - AI and Society 25 (1):19-26.
    At its centennial in 2001, the American Philosophical Association bravely proclaimed: “Philosophy Matters.” But does it? It won’t unless it reaches the concreteness of everyday life. To do so was Martin Heidegger’s ambition, and one can read Saul Kripke’s books as an attempt to get mainstream American philosophy beyond its abstractions. At length, Kripke’s efforts, on one reading, failed while Heidegger’s remained incomplete. A theory of commodification can get us closer to the things that matter to us in everyday life.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. The Dogmatism Puzzle Undone.James Simpson - forthcoming - Analytic Philosophy.
    According to the dogmatism puzzle, for any S and any p, if S knows that p, then she’s entitled to be dogmatic about p, and so disregard any evidence against p, for she knows that (or is in a position to know that) that evidence is misleading. But this seems clearly problematically dogmatic. The standard solution to the dogmatism puzzle involves appealing to the view that acquiring new evidence (even misleading evidence) can undermine one’s knowledge that p. That’s why one (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  90
    Action, Ethics, and Responsibility.Joseph Keim Campbell, Michael O'Rourke & Harry Silverstein (eds.) - 2010 - Bradford.
    Most philosophical explorations of responsibility discuss the topic solely in terms of metaphysics and the "free will" problem. By contrast, these essays by leading philosophers view responsibility from a variety of perspectives -- metaphysics, ethics, action theory, and the philosophy of law. After a broad, framing introduction by the volume's editors, the contributors consider such subjects as responsibility as it relates to the "free will" problem; the relation between responsibility and knowledge or ignorance; the relation between causal and moral responsibility; (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. (1 other version)Critical Notice: Catholicism and Liberalism by R. Bruce Douglass and David Hollenbach.T. Zenzinger - 2000 - Auslegung 23 (1):115-128.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 935